Is studying a free group (or other free object) equivalent to considering only the consequences of the basic...











up vote
3
down vote

favorite












I'm trying to get a better understanding of the rationale behind free groups, and more generally free objects.



This answer does a great job at explaining how various free objects are built, and I understand that one builds a set of "words", and defines an operation over this set, imposing only that a specific set of rules are satisfied.



This makes me wonder: is this construction with words really necessary, or is its only purpose to have a "concrete" object to reason with?



In other words, is studying a free (say) group equivalent to analysing what exactly can be said about a group, without attaching any specific meaning/interpretation to the group elements, so that the elements of the group are effectively only arbitrary symbols, and only the number of such symbols matters?



Along the same lines, when people say that $mathbb Z$ is a free Abelian group, is this statement effectively equivalent to be saying that $mathbb Z$ is entirely defined by its property of being an Abelian group with a single generator?










share|cite|improve this question
























  • You got the general idea. There may be subtleties having to do with constructivity and infinities.
    – Somos
    5 hours ago












  • I don't know what you mean by "really necessary."
    – Qiaochu Yuan
    4 hours ago










  • I would say "characterized" (and then only up to isomorphism) rather than "defined".
    – Derek Elkins
    4 hours ago










  • @QiaochuYuan I mean something on the lines of: can any result about free groups be derived via solely their "equational properties", without any reference to the model with words, or does defining a free group with "words" bring in more structure than that given by only saying "we are dealing with a group with a given number of generators", without making any statement about what the group or the generators "actually are"?
    – glS
    3 hours ago












  • @glS: I don't know what you mean by "more structure." I try to avoid working with words as much as possible myself, although lots of people prove facts about free groups with them. Here's an example of a result about free groups I don't know how to prove via solely "equational properties": every subgroup of a free group is free. Note that the corresponding result for free objects in other settings is false, e.g. subgroups of free commutative rings are usually not free. So there is something special about groups here.
    – Qiaochu Yuan
    3 hours ago















up vote
3
down vote

favorite












I'm trying to get a better understanding of the rationale behind free groups, and more generally free objects.



This answer does a great job at explaining how various free objects are built, and I understand that one builds a set of "words", and defines an operation over this set, imposing only that a specific set of rules are satisfied.



This makes me wonder: is this construction with words really necessary, or is its only purpose to have a "concrete" object to reason with?



In other words, is studying a free (say) group equivalent to analysing what exactly can be said about a group, without attaching any specific meaning/interpretation to the group elements, so that the elements of the group are effectively only arbitrary symbols, and only the number of such symbols matters?



Along the same lines, when people say that $mathbb Z$ is a free Abelian group, is this statement effectively equivalent to be saying that $mathbb Z$ is entirely defined by its property of being an Abelian group with a single generator?










share|cite|improve this question
























  • You got the general idea. There may be subtleties having to do with constructivity and infinities.
    – Somos
    5 hours ago












  • I don't know what you mean by "really necessary."
    – Qiaochu Yuan
    4 hours ago










  • I would say "characterized" (and then only up to isomorphism) rather than "defined".
    – Derek Elkins
    4 hours ago










  • @QiaochuYuan I mean something on the lines of: can any result about free groups be derived via solely their "equational properties", without any reference to the model with words, or does defining a free group with "words" bring in more structure than that given by only saying "we are dealing with a group with a given number of generators", without making any statement about what the group or the generators "actually are"?
    – glS
    3 hours ago












  • @glS: I don't know what you mean by "more structure." I try to avoid working with words as much as possible myself, although lots of people prove facts about free groups with them. Here's an example of a result about free groups I don't know how to prove via solely "equational properties": every subgroup of a free group is free. Note that the corresponding result for free objects in other settings is false, e.g. subgroups of free commutative rings are usually not free. So there is something special about groups here.
    – Qiaochu Yuan
    3 hours ago













up vote
3
down vote

favorite









up vote
3
down vote

favorite











I'm trying to get a better understanding of the rationale behind free groups, and more generally free objects.



This answer does a great job at explaining how various free objects are built, and I understand that one builds a set of "words", and defines an operation over this set, imposing only that a specific set of rules are satisfied.



This makes me wonder: is this construction with words really necessary, or is its only purpose to have a "concrete" object to reason with?



In other words, is studying a free (say) group equivalent to analysing what exactly can be said about a group, without attaching any specific meaning/interpretation to the group elements, so that the elements of the group are effectively only arbitrary symbols, and only the number of such symbols matters?



Along the same lines, when people say that $mathbb Z$ is a free Abelian group, is this statement effectively equivalent to be saying that $mathbb Z$ is entirely defined by its property of being an Abelian group with a single generator?










share|cite|improve this question















I'm trying to get a better understanding of the rationale behind free groups, and more generally free objects.



This answer does a great job at explaining how various free objects are built, and I understand that one builds a set of "words", and defines an operation over this set, imposing only that a specific set of rules are satisfied.



This makes me wonder: is this construction with words really necessary, or is its only purpose to have a "concrete" object to reason with?



In other words, is studying a free (say) group equivalent to analysing what exactly can be said about a group, without attaching any specific meaning/interpretation to the group elements, so that the elements of the group are effectively only arbitrary symbols, and only the number of such symbols matters?



Along the same lines, when people say that $mathbb Z$ is a free Abelian group, is this statement effectively equivalent to be saying that $mathbb Z$ is entirely defined by its property of being an Abelian group with a single generator?







abstract-algebra group-theory free-groups free-abelian-group






share|cite|improve this question















share|cite|improve this question













share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question








edited 3 hours ago

























asked 5 hours ago









glS

707520




707520












  • You got the general idea. There may be subtleties having to do with constructivity and infinities.
    – Somos
    5 hours ago












  • I don't know what you mean by "really necessary."
    – Qiaochu Yuan
    4 hours ago










  • I would say "characterized" (and then only up to isomorphism) rather than "defined".
    – Derek Elkins
    4 hours ago










  • @QiaochuYuan I mean something on the lines of: can any result about free groups be derived via solely their "equational properties", without any reference to the model with words, or does defining a free group with "words" bring in more structure than that given by only saying "we are dealing with a group with a given number of generators", without making any statement about what the group or the generators "actually are"?
    – glS
    3 hours ago












  • @glS: I don't know what you mean by "more structure." I try to avoid working with words as much as possible myself, although lots of people prove facts about free groups with them. Here's an example of a result about free groups I don't know how to prove via solely "equational properties": every subgroup of a free group is free. Note that the corresponding result for free objects in other settings is false, e.g. subgroups of free commutative rings are usually not free. So there is something special about groups here.
    – Qiaochu Yuan
    3 hours ago


















  • You got the general idea. There may be subtleties having to do with constructivity and infinities.
    – Somos
    5 hours ago












  • I don't know what you mean by "really necessary."
    – Qiaochu Yuan
    4 hours ago










  • I would say "characterized" (and then only up to isomorphism) rather than "defined".
    – Derek Elkins
    4 hours ago










  • @QiaochuYuan I mean something on the lines of: can any result about free groups be derived via solely their "equational properties", without any reference to the model with words, or does defining a free group with "words" bring in more structure than that given by only saying "we are dealing with a group with a given number of generators", without making any statement about what the group or the generators "actually are"?
    – glS
    3 hours ago












  • @glS: I don't know what you mean by "more structure." I try to avoid working with words as much as possible myself, although lots of people prove facts about free groups with them. Here's an example of a result about free groups I don't know how to prove via solely "equational properties": every subgroup of a free group is free. Note that the corresponding result for free objects in other settings is false, e.g. subgroups of free commutative rings are usually not free. So there is something special about groups here.
    – Qiaochu Yuan
    3 hours ago
















You got the general idea. There may be subtleties having to do with constructivity and infinities.
– Somos
5 hours ago






You got the general idea. There may be subtleties having to do with constructivity and infinities.
– Somos
5 hours ago














I don't know what you mean by "really necessary."
– Qiaochu Yuan
4 hours ago




I don't know what you mean by "really necessary."
– Qiaochu Yuan
4 hours ago












I would say "characterized" (and then only up to isomorphism) rather than "defined".
– Derek Elkins
4 hours ago




I would say "characterized" (and then only up to isomorphism) rather than "defined".
– Derek Elkins
4 hours ago












@QiaochuYuan I mean something on the lines of: can any result about free groups be derived via solely their "equational properties", without any reference to the model with words, or does defining a free group with "words" bring in more structure than that given by only saying "we are dealing with a group with a given number of generators", without making any statement about what the group or the generators "actually are"?
– glS
3 hours ago






@QiaochuYuan I mean something on the lines of: can any result about free groups be derived via solely their "equational properties", without any reference to the model with words, or does defining a free group with "words" bring in more structure than that given by only saying "we are dealing with a group with a given number of generators", without making any statement about what the group or the generators "actually are"?
– glS
3 hours ago














@glS: I don't know what you mean by "more structure." I try to avoid working with words as much as possible myself, although lots of people prove facts about free groups with them. Here's an example of a result about free groups I don't know how to prove via solely "equational properties": every subgroup of a free group is free. Note that the corresponding result for free objects in other settings is false, e.g. subgroups of free commutative rings are usually not free. So there is something special about groups here.
– Qiaochu Yuan
3 hours ago




@glS: I don't know what you mean by "more structure." I try to avoid working with words as much as possible myself, although lots of people prove facts about free groups with them. Here's an example of a result about free groups I don't know how to prove via solely "equational properties": every subgroup of a free group is free. Note that the corresponding result for free objects in other settings is false, e.g. subgroups of free commutative rings are usually not free. So there is something special about groups here.
– Qiaochu Yuan
3 hours ago










2 Answers
2






active

oldest

votes

















up vote
5
down vote













In a sense yes, studying a free object is very similar to studying the underlying equational theory : as you mentioned, a free group on one generator ($mathbb{Z}$) is the most general thing you get when you think of a group generated by one element.



But that sense is very limited, in that it seems like you want to restrict the study of an object to its equational theory. Free objects are much richer than that, and from time to time, having a concrete model for a free object (say reduced words for the free group) can sbe vert useful, even if most of the time the universal property is enough to get by.



An example that comes up way more often than one might think at first sight is the free (commutative, unital) ring on $n$ generators. One model for it is $mathbb{Z}[X_1,...,X_n]$, and this ring has (non equational) properties that are really interesting (its equational properties "aren't interesting", in that they're just the equational properties of any ring with $n$ fixed elements), for instance it's an integral domain, which allows us to use its fraction field in many arguments concerning general rings, and this comes in quite handy.



I don't know how "useful" you think that can be, but the "reduced words" model for the free group on $n$ generators allows us to prove that $F_2$ (free group on $2$ generators) contains a free group on $3$, or even infinitely many generators !



So yes, the free object on $n$ generators is "entirely defined by its property of being an object and having $n$ generators", and yes its equational theory is not more interesting than simply the equational theory you're considering; but it can have some nontrivial/interesting non equational properties that can be very useful, or at the very least interesting.






share|cite|improve this answer





















  • you write "and yes its equational theory is not more interesting than simply the equational theory you're considering; but it can have some nontrivial/interesting non equational properties that can be very useful, or at the very least interesting.". Why isn't this a contradiction? I don't understand whether the "equational theory" is all there is with a free group or not. It looks like you are saying it is, but then you mention that there is more than that in the case e.g. of $mathbb Z[X_1,...,x_n]$. I'm confused
    – glS
    3 hours ago




















up vote
0
down vote













I am not a hundred percent sure this answers your question, but the Tarski problem asks whether or not the first order theory of nonabelian free groups are equivalent. This was answered in the affirmative by two groups independently: Kharlampovich-Myasnikov and Sela (spanning hundreds of pages). While proving this they also showed that there are groups with the same first order theory as free groups, but not free! As an example surface groups also satisfy the same first order theory.



So from the perspective of elementary theories you can not tell $F_2,F_3$ or $pi_1(Sigma_2)=langle a_1,b_1,a_2,b_2 mid a_1b_1a_1^{-1}b_1^{-1}a_2b_2a_2^{-1}b_2^{-1} rangle$ apart! This should tell you just first order equations is very restrictive, and there are certainly a lot more to these groups than that.



You may be interested in this mathoverflow question too.






share|cite|improve this answer























  • A question and answer on real closed fields might be of interest too, since the first order theory stuff might be more intuitive
    – Paul Plummer
    45 mins ago











Your Answer





StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function () {
return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function () {
StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix) {
StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
});
});
}, "mathjax-editing");

StackExchange.ready(function() {
var channelOptions = {
tags: "".split(" "),
id: "69"
};
initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
// Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
createEditor();
});
}
else {
createEditor();
}
});

function createEditor() {
StackExchange.prepareEditor({
heartbeatType: 'answer',
convertImagesToLinks: true,
noModals: true,
showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
reputationToPostImages: 10,
bindNavPrevention: true,
postfix: "",
imageUploader: {
brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
allowUrls: true
},
noCode: true, onDemand: true,
discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
});


}
});














draft saved

draft discarded


















StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3024795%2fis-studying-a-free-group-or-other-free-object-equivalent-to-considering-only-t%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);

Post as a guest















Required, but never shown

























2 Answers
2






active

oldest

votes








2 Answers
2






active

oldest

votes









active

oldest

votes






active

oldest

votes








up vote
5
down vote













In a sense yes, studying a free object is very similar to studying the underlying equational theory : as you mentioned, a free group on one generator ($mathbb{Z}$) is the most general thing you get when you think of a group generated by one element.



But that sense is very limited, in that it seems like you want to restrict the study of an object to its equational theory. Free objects are much richer than that, and from time to time, having a concrete model for a free object (say reduced words for the free group) can sbe vert useful, even if most of the time the universal property is enough to get by.



An example that comes up way more often than one might think at first sight is the free (commutative, unital) ring on $n$ generators. One model for it is $mathbb{Z}[X_1,...,X_n]$, and this ring has (non equational) properties that are really interesting (its equational properties "aren't interesting", in that they're just the equational properties of any ring with $n$ fixed elements), for instance it's an integral domain, which allows us to use its fraction field in many arguments concerning general rings, and this comes in quite handy.



I don't know how "useful" you think that can be, but the "reduced words" model for the free group on $n$ generators allows us to prove that $F_2$ (free group on $2$ generators) contains a free group on $3$, or even infinitely many generators !



So yes, the free object on $n$ generators is "entirely defined by its property of being an object and having $n$ generators", and yes its equational theory is not more interesting than simply the equational theory you're considering; but it can have some nontrivial/interesting non equational properties that can be very useful, or at the very least interesting.






share|cite|improve this answer





















  • you write "and yes its equational theory is not more interesting than simply the equational theory you're considering; but it can have some nontrivial/interesting non equational properties that can be very useful, or at the very least interesting.". Why isn't this a contradiction? I don't understand whether the "equational theory" is all there is with a free group or not. It looks like you are saying it is, but then you mention that there is more than that in the case e.g. of $mathbb Z[X_1,...,x_n]$. I'm confused
    – glS
    3 hours ago

















up vote
5
down vote













In a sense yes, studying a free object is very similar to studying the underlying equational theory : as you mentioned, a free group on one generator ($mathbb{Z}$) is the most general thing you get when you think of a group generated by one element.



But that sense is very limited, in that it seems like you want to restrict the study of an object to its equational theory. Free objects are much richer than that, and from time to time, having a concrete model for a free object (say reduced words for the free group) can sbe vert useful, even if most of the time the universal property is enough to get by.



An example that comes up way more often than one might think at first sight is the free (commutative, unital) ring on $n$ generators. One model for it is $mathbb{Z}[X_1,...,X_n]$, and this ring has (non equational) properties that are really interesting (its equational properties "aren't interesting", in that they're just the equational properties of any ring with $n$ fixed elements), for instance it's an integral domain, which allows us to use its fraction field in many arguments concerning general rings, and this comes in quite handy.



I don't know how "useful" you think that can be, but the "reduced words" model for the free group on $n$ generators allows us to prove that $F_2$ (free group on $2$ generators) contains a free group on $3$, or even infinitely many generators !



So yes, the free object on $n$ generators is "entirely defined by its property of being an object and having $n$ generators", and yes its equational theory is not more interesting than simply the equational theory you're considering; but it can have some nontrivial/interesting non equational properties that can be very useful, or at the very least interesting.






share|cite|improve this answer





















  • you write "and yes its equational theory is not more interesting than simply the equational theory you're considering; but it can have some nontrivial/interesting non equational properties that can be very useful, or at the very least interesting.". Why isn't this a contradiction? I don't understand whether the "equational theory" is all there is with a free group or not. It looks like you are saying it is, but then you mention that there is more than that in the case e.g. of $mathbb Z[X_1,...,x_n]$. I'm confused
    – glS
    3 hours ago















up vote
5
down vote










up vote
5
down vote









In a sense yes, studying a free object is very similar to studying the underlying equational theory : as you mentioned, a free group on one generator ($mathbb{Z}$) is the most general thing you get when you think of a group generated by one element.



But that sense is very limited, in that it seems like you want to restrict the study of an object to its equational theory. Free objects are much richer than that, and from time to time, having a concrete model for a free object (say reduced words for the free group) can sbe vert useful, even if most of the time the universal property is enough to get by.



An example that comes up way more often than one might think at first sight is the free (commutative, unital) ring on $n$ generators. One model for it is $mathbb{Z}[X_1,...,X_n]$, and this ring has (non equational) properties that are really interesting (its equational properties "aren't interesting", in that they're just the equational properties of any ring with $n$ fixed elements), for instance it's an integral domain, which allows us to use its fraction field in many arguments concerning general rings, and this comes in quite handy.



I don't know how "useful" you think that can be, but the "reduced words" model for the free group on $n$ generators allows us to prove that $F_2$ (free group on $2$ generators) contains a free group on $3$, or even infinitely many generators !



So yes, the free object on $n$ generators is "entirely defined by its property of being an object and having $n$ generators", and yes its equational theory is not more interesting than simply the equational theory you're considering; but it can have some nontrivial/interesting non equational properties that can be very useful, or at the very least interesting.






share|cite|improve this answer












In a sense yes, studying a free object is very similar to studying the underlying equational theory : as you mentioned, a free group on one generator ($mathbb{Z}$) is the most general thing you get when you think of a group generated by one element.



But that sense is very limited, in that it seems like you want to restrict the study of an object to its equational theory. Free objects are much richer than that, and from time to time, having a concrete model for a free object (say reduced words for the free group) can sbe vert useful, even if most of the time the universal property is enough to get by.



An example that comes up way more often than one might think at first sight is the free (commutative, unital) ring on $n$ generators. One model for it is $mathbb{Z}[X_1,...,X_n]$, and this ring has (non equational) properties that are really interesting (its equational properties "aren't interesting", in that they're just the equational properties of any ring with $n$ fixed elements), for instance it's an integral domain, which allows us to use its fraction field in many arguments concerning general rings, and this comes in quite handy.



I don't know how "useful" you think that can be, but the "reduced words" model for the free group on $n$ generators allows us to prove that $F_2$ (free group on $2$ generators) contains a free group on $3$, or even infinitely many generators !



So yes, the free object on $n$ generators is "entirely defined by its property of being an object and having $n$ generators", and yes its equational theory is not more interesting than simply the equational theory you're considering; but it can have some nontrivial/interesting non equational properties that can be very useful, or at the very least interesting.







share|cite|improve this answer












share|cite|improve this answer



share|cite|improve this answer










answered 4 hours ago









Max

12.4k11040




12.4k11040












  • you write "and yes its equational theory is not more interesting than simply the equational theory you're considering; but it can have some nontrivial/interesting non equational properties that can be very useful, or at the very least interesting.". Why isn't this a contradiction? I don't understand whether the "equational theory" is all there is with a free group or not. It looks like you are saying it is, but then you mention that there is more than that in the case e.g. of $mathbb Z[X_1,...,x_n]$. I'm confused
    – glS
    3 hours ago




















  • you write "and yes its equational theory is not more interesting than simply the equational theory you're considering; but it can have some nontrivial/interesting non equational properties that can be very useful, or at the very least interesting.". Why isn't this a contradiction? I don't understand whether the "equational theory" is all there is with a free group or not. It looks like you are saying it is, but then you mention that there is more than that in the case e.g. of $mathbb Z[X_1,...,x_n]$. I'm confused
    – glS
    3 hours ago


















you write "and yes its equational theory is not more interesting than simply the equational theory you're considering; but it can have some nontrivial/interesting non equational properties that can be very useful, or at the very least interesting.". Why isn't this a contradiction? I don't understand whether the "equational theory" is all there is with a free group or not. It looks like you are saying it is, but then you mention that there is more than that in the case e.g. of $mathbb Z[X_1,...,x_n]$. I'm confused
– glS
3 hours ago






you write "and yes its equational theory is not more interesting than simply the equational theory you're considering; but it can have some nontrivial/interesting non equational properties that can be very useful, or at the very least interesting.". Why isn't this a contradiction? I don't understand whether the "equational theory" is all there is with a free group or not. It looks like you are saying it is, but then you mention that there is more than that in the case e.g. of $mathbb Z[X_1,...,x_n]$. I'm confused
– glS
3 hours ago












up vote
0
down vote













I am not a hundred percent sure this answers your question, but the Tarski problem asks whether or not the first order theory of nonabelian free groups are equivalent. This was answered in the affirmative by two groups independently: Kharlampovich-Myasnikov and Sela (spanning hundreds of pages). While proving this they also showed that there are groups with the same first order theory as free groups, but not free! As an example surface groups also satisfy the same first order theory.



So from the perspective of elementary theories you can not tell $F_2,F_3$ or $pi_1(Sigma_2)=langle a_1,b_1,a_2,b_2 mid a_1b_1a_1^{-1}b_1^{-1}a_2b_2a_2^{-1}b_2^{-1} rangle$ apart! This should tell you just first order equations is very restrictive, and there are certainly a lot more to these groups than that.



You may be interested in this mathoverflow question too.






share|cite|improve this answer























  • A question and answer on real closed fields might be of interest too, since the first order theory stuff might be more intuitive
    – Paul Plummer
    45 mins ago















up vote
0
down vote













I am not a hundred percent sure this answers your question, but the Tarski problem asks whether or not the first order theory of nonabelian free groups are equivalent. This was answered in the affirmative by two groups independently: Kharlampovich-Myasnikov and Sela (spanning hundreds of pages). While proving this they also showed that there are groups with the same first order theory as free groups, but not free! As an example surface groups also satisfy the same first order theory.



So from the perspective of elementary theories you can not tell $F_2,F_3$ or $pi_1(Sigma_2)=langle a_1,b_1,a_2,b_2 mid a_1b_1a_1^{-1}b_1^{-1}a_2b_2a_2^{-1}b_2^{-1} rangle$ apart! This should tell you just first order equations is very restrictive, and there are certainly a lot more to these groups than that.



You may be interested in this mathoverflow question too.






share|cite|improve this answer























  • A question and answer on real closed fields might be of interest too, since the first order theory stuff might be more intuitive
    – Paul Plummer
    45 mins ago













up vote
0
down vote










up vote
0
down vote









I am not a hundred percent sure this answers your question, but the Tarski problem asks whether or not the first order theory of nonabelian free groups are equivalent. This was answered in the affirmative by two groups independently: Kharlampovich-Myasnikov and Sela (spanning hundreds of pages). While proving this they also showed that there are groups with the same first order theory as free groups, but not free! As an example surface groups also satisfy the same first order theory.



So from the perspective of elementary theories you can not tell $F_2,F_3$ or $pi_1(Sigma_2)=langle a_1,b_1,a_2,b_2 mid a_1b_1a_1^{-1}b_1^{-1}a_2b_2a_2^{-1}b_2^{-1} rangle$ apart! This should tell you just first order equations is very restrictive, and there are certainly a lot more to these groups than that.



You may be interested in this mathoverflow question too.






share|cite|improve this answer














I am not a hundred percent sure this answers your question, but the Tarski problem asks whether or not the first order theory of nonabelian free groups are equivalent. This was answered in the affirmative by two groups independently: Kharlampovich-Myasnikov and Sela (spanning hundreds of pages). While proving this they also showed that there are groups with the same first order theory as free groups, but not free! As an example surface groups also satisfy the same first order theory.



So from the perspective of elementary theories you can not tell $F_2,F_3$ or $pi_1(Sigma_2)=langle a_1,b_1,a_2,b_2 mid a_1b_1a_1^{-1}b_1^{-1}a_2b_2a_2^{-1}b_2^{-1} rangle$ apart! This should tell you just first order equations is very restrictive, and there are certainly a lot more to these groups than that.



You may be interested in this mathoverflow question too.







share|cite|improve this answer














share|cite|improve this answer



share|cite|improve this answer








edited 1 hour ago

























answered 1 hour ago









Paul Plummer

4,86721950




4,86721950












  • A question and answer on real closed fields might be of interest too, since the first order theory stuff might be more intuitive
    – Paul Plummer
    45 mins ago


















  • A question and answer on real closed fields might be of interest too, since the first order theory stuff might be more intuitive
    – Paul Plummer
    45 mins ago
















A question and answer on real closed fields might be of interest too, since the first order theory stuff might be more intuitive
– Paul Plummer
45 mins ago




A question and answer on real closed fields might be of interest too, since the first order theory stuff might be more intuitive
– Paul Plummer
45 mins ago


















draft saved

draft discarded




















































Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!


  • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

But avoid



  • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

  • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.


Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.


To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.





Some of your past answers have not been well-received, and you're in danger of being blocked from answering.


Please pay close attention to the following guidance:


  • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

But avoid



  • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

  • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.


To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.




draft saved


draft discarded














StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3024795%2fis-studying-a-free-group-or-other-free-object-equivalent-to-considering-only-t%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);

Post as a guest















Required, but never shown





















































Required, but never shown














Required, but never shown












Required, but never shown







Required, but never shown

































Required, but never shown














Required, but never shown












Required, but never shown







Required, but never shown







Popular posts from this blog

404 Error Contact Form 7 ajax form submitting

How to know if a Active Directory user can login interactively

TypeError: fit_transform() missing 1 required positional argument: 'X'